Alice C. Linsley
Timeline
Thales 624 BC - 546 BC
Heraclitus 535 BC - 475 BC
Gorgias 483 BC - 375 BC
Protagoras 480 BC - 411 BC
Socrates 469 BC - 399 BC
Democritus 460 BC - 370 BC
Plato 428 BC - 347 BC
Aristotle 384 BC - 322 BC
Zeno 333 BC - 264 BC
Thales 624 BC - 546 BC
Heraclitus 535 BC - 475 BC
Gorgias 483 BC - 375 BC
Protagoras 480 BC - 411 BC
Socrates 469 BC - 399 BC
Democritus 460 BC - 370 BC
Plato 428 BC - 347 BC
Aristotle 384 BC - 322 BC
Zeno 333 BC - 264 BC
The Pre-Socratic Philosophers
Aristotle regarded Thales of Miletus as the first
philosopher in the Greek tradition. Bertrand Russell believed that
"Western philosophy begins with Thales." Thales attempted to explain
natural phenomena without reference to mythology, an approach that was not
typical of his time. His interest in astronomy was such that he reportedly fell into a ditch or well while contemplating the stars. Plato wrote of how he was mocked for this by a servant. "Just like Thales … while star gazing and looking up he fell in a well, and some gracefully witty Thracian servant girl is said to have made a jest at his expense—that in his eagerness to know the things in heaven he was unaware of the things in front of him and at his feet. The same jest suffices for all those who engage in philosophy.” (Plato,Theaetetus 174a, Seth Benardete translation)
The philosophers before Socrates were largely concerned with
discovering universal principles which would explain the whole of nature. Thales believed that all things derive from a single first cause or source which he called arche or archai. Anaximander (c. 611-546 BC) held that the basic substance of the universe is an eternal and imperishable apeiron from which all things are born and to which all things return. Heraclitus, who believed that all things are in a state of change, used the word logos. We might regard these views as metaphysical attempts at a “unified field theory.”
The Greek
City State
The Greeks were organized politically by principal cities which had oversight of the surrounded region. Each city state (polis) was autonomous and self-governing. This corresponded to a similar system of organization along the Nile called "nomes." There were no nations as we know them today. There were dominions or empires under the control of great kingdom builders such as Darius the Great. Often the conqueror permitted the ruler of the city state to remain in power after swearing an oath of loyalty and agreeing to pay tribute.
The Greeks were proud of their culture and were suspicious of outsiders (xenophobia). Although they shared a common language and culture, each city state had its own customs, deities, money and army. A citizen’s first loyalty was to his city state and to the deity to whom the local temple was dedicated. Many of the festivals of the city states were religious in nature. The populace enjoyed processions through the streets much as Americans enjoy Fourth of July parades.Temples were the centers of much daily
activity, with priests offering sacrifices and libations, and people coming
and going to fulfill their sacred duties. Life was generally good since everyone knew his or her place
in the hierarchical social order, and the communities were small enough to
sustain economic prosperity in spite of Greece's rocky farm land.
The primary foods sources were lamb, fish, bread, cheeses, yogurt, grapes, figs, dates, olives, olive oil, and wine.
The Greeks were proud of their culture and were suspicious of outsiders (xenophobia). Although they shared a common language and culture, each city state had its own customs, deities, money and army. A citizen’s first loyalty was to his city state and to the deity to whom the local temple was dedicated. Many of the festivals of the city states were religious in nature. The populace enjoyed processions through the streets much as Americans enjoy Fourth of July parades.
The primary foods sources were lamb, fish, bread, cheeses, yogurt, grapes, figs, dates, olives, olive oil, and wine.
The Influence of Nilotic Thought
Much of the wisdom of the ancient Greeks was received from the priests of the Nile Valley . The four most famous temple universities were Onn (Heliopolis ), Inbu Hedj (Memphis ), Ipet Isut (Karnak) and Waset (Thebes ). The Greeks recognized the wisdom of these places to be very ancient and venerable.
Cultural contact between the Greeks and the Egyptians on the island of Crete has been verified from at least 2600 BC. There was artistic and iconographic exchange between Minoans and Egyptians around 1700 BC.
Cultural contact between the Greeks and the Egyptians on the island of Crete has been verified from at least 2600 BC. There was artistic and iconographic exchange between Minoans and Egyptians around 1700 BC.
Thales visited Egypt and calculated the height of the pyramids from the length of their shadows. Hippocrates, called the father of medicine, studied the healing arts in Egypt . Democritus visited Egypt and wrote on ancient Nubia or Kemet. He praised the Egyptian mathematicians.
According to Iamblichus, Thales insisted that Pythagorus study in Egypt because the priests there were esteemed for their knowledge and wisdom. Plato studied in Egypt for thirteen years under the priest Sechnuphis. It is likely that Plato’s conception of the eternal Forms was based on Horite Hebrew binary metaphysics.
Priests and Oracles
While priests and oracles provided guidance and influenced
ethical decision making, they did not fully satisfy human curiosity about the
nature of the world. Nor did they offer
a satisfying response to those who thought that the gods seemed too human and
fallible, as did Democritus and Socrates.
The Pre-Socratic Worldview
To grasp the significance of Socrates’ contribution to
ethics it is necessary to understand how the ancient Greeks viewed their world.
We gain insight into their worldview by reading Homer’s epic poem, The Iliad. This bloody account of
the battles between the Trojans and the Greeks seems a strange tale to modern
readers because it weaves together history, religion and mythology. Yet this was an aspect of the Greek worldview
in Homer’s time. People believed in a
world in which the gods regularly intervened in human affairs, sometimes
whisking away heroic warriors in their chariots and often joining in the battle
themselves. Some heroes were regarded as
semi-divine beings. Priests sacrificed
animals and made other offerings in the temples to gain the favor of the gods,
and oracles were consulted for the most auspicious days on which to wage war or
make peace. People did not choose who they would marry. They married within their social class or
caste. Nor did people select their line
of work. They inherited the work they
did from their fathers. If one’s father
was a metal smith, his sons would be smiths also. This was especially the case with firstborn
sons.
Before Socrates, people were losing confidence in the old
order of gods and in their leaders. The social order was changing from one in
which each person’s social status and line of work were fixed according to a
rigid caste system to one in which nobility of character or special gifts sometimes opened opportunities that were not available to earlier generations
of Greeks. In the old order, a good
citizen was someone who fulfilled his role in the caste system. A street sweeper
was a good sweeper if he rose early and efficiently cleaned the streets
assigned to him. A nobleman was a good
ruler if he ordered his household well, spoke persuasively in public, and
participated in the forums. As the old social order began to break down, it
became necessary to re-think what it meant to be a good citizen and what
constituted a good life. Social change and political disruption stimulated
ethical conversations and began to lay the foundation for philosophy and ethics
in Western Civilization.
Transition to the Classical Period
Before the time of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle, Greek
citizens were defined by their place in the hierarchical caste system that was
typical of the ancient Mediterranean world. Because one did not marry outside one’s caste and continued in the same
work as one’s father, the pre-classical social order was stable and Greek
citizens shared common ideas of good and evil, and right and wrong.
With the emergence of the Greek city-states, Athens being an example,
the social order began to change. Each city-state developed a social and
political order independent of outside political authority. Each established
foreign trade that brought an influx of non-Greeks into the cities, introducing
different customs, ways of life and moral attitudes.What was acceptable in one
city might be offensive in the next. Law codes differed from city to city, and
traditional Greek values and beliefs were found to be incompatible with those
of other cultures. In this new order the Greek citizen was presented with many
conflicting truth claims. It was a
social landscape ripe for the proliferation of many ethical philosophies.
The Sophists
The period of the Sophists was one in which people had
doubts about whether the social order of their fathers should to be regarded as
the best order and divinely appointed. People believed that attempts to rise above one’s caste would bring the
wrath of the gods upon them, since the social order was regarded as having been
established by the gods. This is one reason that the lower classes didn’t rebel
against their rulers. If the
hierarchical castes of the ancient Mediterranean world were not divinely
appointed, then how was one to live as a good citizen in this new world? The Sophists attempted to provide practical
answers to this question.
The Sophists
came to prominence in the 5th century, B.C. Unlike Socrates and Plato, they
were not philosophers, but teachers of “rhetoric” which is the art of public
speaking and persuasion. Sophistry was a school of thought that emphasized how
to be successful in the new order. The Sophists did not claim to be
philosophers, but teachers of socially useful skills such as how to order one’s
household, how to keep good accounts, how to speak persuasively and how to
dress for success.
A Sophist about whom we know a good deal through Plato’s
writings is Protagoras
(480-411 BC). He said that, “Man is the measure of all things.” By this he intended that everyone should
“measure” or decide matters according to his own nature and needs. When applied
to ethics and morality, this idea leads to “moral relativism.” Relativism doubts the possibility of
discovering absolute truth. If there is no absolute truth for all people, at
all times, and in all places, why waste time trying to teach truth? Instead Sophists trained students for worldly
success. You might say that Protagoras was the head of the school of “how
to make a good impression.” Students who
studied Sophistry gained social, political and economic power in Athens , because they were
trained to win oral arguments and to conduct their personal affairs so as to
achieve status. Many Sophists claimed they could teach anything and its
opposite (thesis and antithesis) and could win debates by making the weaker
argument the stronger.
Another Sophist was Gorgias (483-375 BC), a great
cynic. He said, “Nothing exists, and if it did, no one could know it, and if
they knew it, they could not communicate it.” Gorgias’ view is called “nihilism,” from the Greek word “nihil” which
means nothing. Nihilism denies that there is any truth and therefore rejects
all truth claims. When a person claims to have discovered something that is
true, they also claim that truth as an authority for themselves. However, if no
truth exists, there is no ground for authority. When applied to ethics and
morality, nihilism leads to a philosophical dead end. If, in the end, there is
really nothing, there is nothing to discuss. When applied to politics, nihilism
leads to anarchy. If, in the end, there is no authority, there is no basis for
trust in government.
Socrates questions morality of the art of persuasion
The Sophists believed that moral goodness consists of public
recognition and success. They were not especially interested in questions of
Good and Evil. Instead, they sought to prepare young men to become successful
in Athenian society by knowing how to conduct their affairs, dress as a ruler,
and speak eloquently. They sought to
perfect the art of rhetoric. By becoming a persuasive public speaker, an
individual could impress audiences and sway opinion in the public forums held
in the Greek city-states. Many
aristocratic young men were attracted to Sophistry, hoping to gain recognition and
status.
Socrates viewed Sophistry with suspicion. He believed that it wasn’t enough to teach a
man how to dress for success and how to persuade people to your side. In fact,
Socrates thought this was quite dangerous. What if the most successful and persuasive man were to lead the people unwisely,
being ignorant of how to life a good life?
Although Socrates lived before Zeno, he anticipated the
danger of apathy among the citizens of Athens .
His method was to ask well-formed questions that placed a burden on people to
think about their actions and attitudes. Socrates left no writings, so we
cannot consult primary sources to discover exactly what he taught. What we do know comes from three sources: the
historian Xenophan,
his student Plato, and Plato’s student Aristotle.
Xenophan portrays Socrates as an ordinary man interested in
developing good citizens. In his
writings Memorabilia and Symposium, he characterizes Socrates as a popular
ethical teacher who had little interest in logic or metaphysics. Plato portrays
Socrates as more complex. He presents him as a teacher who denies having
disciples, as a lover of beauty who disdains sensual pleasures, and as a man of
reason who listens to the divine.
For ethics, Socrates’ greatest legacy is his consistent and
steadfast belief in the importance of good citizenship. This is exemplified in
the events surrounding his last days. He
had made enemies in Athens
by pointing out the hypocrisy of various prominent figures. Eventually he was falsely accused of morally corrupting the youth. He was brought to
trial and found guilty. What is known of
these final events comes from Plato’s Dialogues, and from his Apology, a record
of the speeches that Socrates delivered at his trial. According to Plato, Socrates admitted that he
could have avoided trial by abandoning philosophy and minding his own business.
After his conviction, he could have avoided death by escaping with the help of
friends, but to Socrates this would have been a denial of everything he had
tried to teach. He cooperated with the
State because this is what a good citizen does. The people of Athens
believed that Socrates was unjustly condemned and this created a problem for
Socrates. If he allowed the State to take his life unjustly, it would undermine
the people’s confidence in government, so rather than permit the State to
execute him, he chose to take his own life. Plato describes as a first hand
witness how Socrates drank a cup of deadly hemlock and laid down and died.
Plato (428 BC - 347 BC)
When Socrates died in 399, Plato gave up all political
ambitions and left Athens , traveling to Italy and Sicily . Soon after his return to Athens , he established his Academy outside
the city. It is often stated that the western university system is based
on Plato’s Academy, but that is to overlook Plato's experience in Egypt. The Nile shrine-cities were recognized by the Greeks as great center of learning.
Plato was a prolific writer who kept Socrates ideas alive in
over 24 writings called “dialogues.” The dialogues range from 20 to 300 pages
and their titles are usually the names of the interlocutor who Socrates
questions. Plato focused Socrates’ moral
arguments in the early dialogues and built on his ideas in the later dialogues.
It is evident from Plato’s writings that he shared Socrates’
preoccupation with clear and precise definition of ethical concepts, and with
knowing how one should live. Plato’s
main disagreement with Socrates has to do with the definition of virtue as
knowledge. Socrates insisted that before we can say anything about justice we
must first answer the question “What is justice?” Plato recognized that asking what justice is
only leads to considering examples of justice and examples of the opposite of
justice. Socrates’ approach never seems to bring us to a substantial definition
of justice. Plato wondered how we are
able to recognize justice when we are unable to define it. He came to the conclusion that an unambiguous
example of justice must exist in the metaphysical (non-material) sense, and
that we must once have known justice as an eternal and unchanging “Form” or we
would not be able to recognize examples of it.
Plato’s Theory of Forms is
based upon his belief that we are born into this material world from an ideal
world where our soul was acquainted with the Forms of Justice, Goodness, Beauty
and Love. We are able to recognize
justice, goodness, beauty and love because our souls have innate knowledge of
these non-material entities. Plato goes
on to explain that the examples we see are only reflections of the Forms, not
the Forms themselves. In other words, justice and goodness are eternal Ideas
that exist whether or not humans recognize them.
What does this mean for ethics? It means that philosophy’s main objective is
to seek knowledge of the true Forms. Plato said that not everyone would do this. He used the allegory of the
cave to explain that some would always be locked in darkness where they are
able to see only shadows. Others will escape to the world of sunlight where
they will see the true form of things.
According to Plato, societal evil is the absence of Good and
can be averted only by enlightened rulers or “Guardians.” The ideal society requires censorship by the
Guardians to protect the weak minded cave dwellers who are unable to discern
the difference between shadow and Form. Plato maintained that a man cannot do Good unless he recognizes the Good
through his soul. The ethical person
judges justice by the measurement of justice known in the eternal soul.
Plato taught that the soul, like the ideal society, has
three parts or levels. The good person is one who ascends from the lowest level
of the soul governed by appetites (what we want and feel) to the rational level
governed by the intellect. The middle level is the “spirited” level which
undertakes whatever the intellect determines to be best. These levels of the
soul correspond to the levels of Plato’s ideal social order. The workers provide all the material needs,
the soldiers ensure that the rulers’ dictates are carried out, and the rulers
discern wisdom and justice through philosophical conversation and inward
contemplation.
In the empirical age, Plato’s metaphysics are largely
rejected and with this comes the rejection of the possibility of a soul as a
reservoir of innate knowledge. Through
the writings of Thomas Aquinas, the West has been more influenced by the thought
of Plato’s student, Aristotle.
Aristotle (384 BC - 322 BC)
Aristotle produced a large number of writings and from these
we are able to recognize his important contribution to Ethics. His contributions
are evident in his understanding of the human as a political creature, and in
his understanding that the chief good is “eudaimonia” (“you-DYE-mon-ee-ah”). The Greek word Eudaimonia (Eudaemonism) refers to a state of having a good indwelling spirit or daemon. This Greek word has been translated as happiness, pleasure, and prosperity, but is better
understood as the flourishing of the individual in every area of life. Aristotle regarded individual happiness as
the highest good, and eudaimonism
continues throughout the history of ethics, with some philosophers building on
Aristotle’s idea and some arguing against it.
The Human as Political Creature
Aristotle regarded Man is the only creature capable of
abstract reasoning. Man can be said to resemble the Unmoved
Mover and higher reasoning should be a first priority for humankind. The exercise of intellectual and moral capacities is essential in order for mankind to flourish as a species. However, capacities such as
just action cannot be exercised outside the context of the state. The state
provides everything necessary for the good life and it exists in nature exactly
for this purpose. Aristotle teaches that the state accords with human nature.
He writes that “that the state belongs to the class of objects which exist by
nature” (Politics I. 2). For Aristotle, humans will always live
in relationship to the state because human beings are essentially political
creatures.
This leads Aristotle to speak of the state as something
supremely superior to the individual, as an entity with individual parts that are
in themselves of little worth. He even says that the citizen belongs to the
state (Politics VIII.1.) This has led to charges that Aristotle advocates
totalitarianism, but that would be to miss the larger picture. Aristotle is not
speaking of the restriction of citizen’s rights, but of the ontological
relationship of citizen and state. We
know this is the case because, unlike Plato, he opposes censorship. Aristotle's view of the state cannot be isolated from his understanding of the human as a political creature.
Personal Happiness as the Highest Good
In Nicomachean Ethics, his chief work on ethics, Aristotle
defines happiness as “an activity of the soul in accord with perfect Virtue.”
For Aristotle, happiness is not a Form, but a process involving decisions about
many goods. He argues that we are
motivated to pursue the good life in order to find personal happiness. Happiness
is not something we arrive at, but something which accompanies certain
activities and choices. Since happiness means something different for every
person, there can’t be a single true Form of happiness. Aristotle’s primary
argument with his teacher Plato is over this question of Forms. Aristotle
doubts their existence.
For Aristotle a flourishing life consists in pleasure,
honor, and virtue. Aristotle argues that
it is virtue that corrects our superficial attraction to pleasure. He also argues that when we want honor what
we really want is to deserve honor. He regards personal happiness or
flourishing as worth pursuing for its own sake. Anything else that we might regard as “good” will ultimately bring us
back to the goal of happiness. Aristotle
believes that it is meaningless to speak of having a good life when one is
unhappy or not flourishing. He is not suggesting that we behave selfishly. In fact, achieving happiness in our lives may
involve personal sacrifice at times, but if we must constantly sacrifice, we
are not going to be happy. This is what
Aristotle intends by his famous statement: “No man can be happy on the rack.”
Aristotle’s “Golden Mean”
If everyone is capable of living the good life, why do we
fail to do so? Aristotle tells us that
the good life requires balance, and balance is different of each person. For example, if eating brings me happiness, I
must discover through experience how eating makes me happy. If I eat too much and become sick or
uncomfortable, I have actually caused myself unhappiness. This is why Aristotle says, “People ought to
behave so as to achieve happiness.” No
one can tell me exactly how to achieve personal happiness. A 125 pound office worker and a 200 pound
farmer will not find happiness by eating the same amount of food each day,
because their physical needs are different.
To us this seems like common sense.
That is why Aristotle is regarded as the first great philosopher with a
common sense approach to ethics.
Aristotle’s “Golden Mean”
is not only about avoiding extremes, it involves discovering what is morally
neutral. We might agree that moderate
drinking of alcohol and only when one intends not to drive is morally neutral. None would agree that drinking alcohol to
excess and driving drunk is morally neutral. For alcohol consumption to
contribute to personal happiness a person must discover exactly how much and
under what circumstances he or she can consume it. Consuming too much alcohol
could leave one feeling sick, which is not a state of happiness or pleasure.
Aristotle’s Golden Mean is about taking personal responsibility for one’s life
and actions.
Implications of Aristotle’s Mean
In The Republic, Plato proposes that all citizens’
fundamental needs can be met by having people specialize in the kind of work
for which they are naturally gifted, rather than requiring them to continue in
the profession of their fathers. He believes
that the grouping of citizens into specialized functions and the prudent
leadership of philosopher kings will produce a just society. This view of justice requires that I bring my
personal happiness into harmony with the best interests of others. This involves some sacrifice. It is difficult to achieve the golden mean
for my life when I must subordinate my happiness to the general welfare of the
state. Further, since the options of a
worker would be much more limited than the options of a ruler, workers would
have less freedom to discover what brings them happiness. In other words, in Plato’s ideal society it
would be difficult to discover one’s golden mean because some activities would
not be lawful.
Here is where we encounter one of the most significant
implications of Aristotle’s golden mean for social ethics. Plato requires that the ideal society impose
censorship to protect the weak minded, and Aristotle believes that censorship
hinders moral decisions by limiting people’s lawful choices. This is consistent with Aristotle’s view that
well-being consists in virtuous actions that stem from a virtuous character. A
virtuous character can only be developed by making wise choices.
Plato and Aristotle hold irreconcilable views on censorship,
and the question of censorship continues to be a point of disagreement even
today. As we will learn in a later lesson, John Stuart Mill’s view of liberty
will be closer to Aristotle’s and Thomas Hobbes’ view will be closer to
Plato’s.
Stoicism
Before concluding this lesson, we must consider the
influence of Zeno (333
BC - 264 BC), a student of the great Cynic Crates, and founder of Stoic
philosophy. He was persuaded to the philosophical life by reading Xenophan’s
description of Socrates in Memorabilia.
Zeno proposed an answer to doubts about the gods and
concerns about the growing instability.
He did not accept the Cynics view that the world is fundamentally evil
and that the only virtue is to find peace within oneself by rejecting worldly
things. Instead he taught that everything is determined by God’s good order in
the universe and that we have no power to change what happens. Therefore whatever happens to the individual,
whether good or bad, should be accepted without desire or strong emotions. Zeno said that “man conquers the world by
conquering himself.”
In the most often quoted explanation of his stoic viewpoint,
Zeno wrote: “God is not separate from the world; He is the soul of the world,
and each of us contains a part of the Divine Fire. All things are parts of one
single system, which is called Nature; the individual life is good when it is
in harmony with Nature. In one sense, every life is in harmony with Nature,
since it is such as Nature’s laws have caused it to be; but in another sense a
human life is only in harmony with Nature when the individual will is directed
to ends which are among those of Nature. Virtue consists in a will which is in
agreement with Nature. The wicked, though perforce they obey God’s law, do so
involuntarily; in the simile of Cleanthes, they are like a dog tied to a cart,
and compelled to go wherever it goes. In the life of an individual man, virtue
is the sole good; such things as health, happiness, possessions, are of no
account. Since virtue resides in the will, everything really good or bad in a
man’s life depends only upon himself. He may be poor, but what of it? He can
still be virtuous. He may be sentenced to death, but he can die nobly, like
Socrates. Other men have power only over externals; virtue, which alone is
truly good, rests entirely with the individual. Therefore every man has perfect
freedom, provided he emancipates himself from mundane desires.”
This is the basis of Stoicism, a philosophical viewpoint
that had profound influence even to the first century of Christianity.
The problem with Stoicism is that it encourages indifferent
acceptance of injustice by making the one true Virtue detachment from the
fortunes of the world. While it is wise
to control strong emotions and to intellectually detach so as to evaluate more
objectively, Stoicism does not stir one to act against injustice and to attempt
to right social wrongs.
Summary
As philosophers debate the differences between Plato and
Aristotle through the centuries, those differences come into focus. Today we see Plato as the “father” of
Platonism and Idealism, and Aristotle as the “father” of Empiricism, which
defines reality on the basis of what can be verified through the senses,
observation or experience. Here we can see the contrast between the viewpoints
of Plato and Aristotle:
Plato regards evil as the lack of knowledge of the Good.
Aristotle regards evil as something people do in violation
of their happiness.
Plato regards morality as intellectual discovery, similar to
mathematics.
Aristotle regards morality as a dynamic exploration of what
brings happiness.
Plato maintains that there is but one Good for all people at
all times (Absolutism).
Aristotle says that the good life will have different expressions,
since what brings happiness is different for all people (Relativism).
Plato believes that only the leisure classes who receive
training in intellectual and moral virtues are capable of knowing the Good.
Aristotle believes that all people have a responsibility to
discover what constitutes the good for them.
Plato believes that the ideal society requires censorship to
protect the weak.
Aristotle believes that censorship hinders the individual’s
moral decision making.
Plato’s ideal king is a ruler who philosophically
contemplates the Forms.
Aristotle’s ideal king is one who seeks the Golden Mean in
both personal and public life.
Plato doubted Socrates definition of virtue as knowledge.
Socrates insisted that before we can say anything about justice we must first
answer the question “What is justice?”
Plato recognized that asking what justice is only leads to considering
examples of justice and examples of injustice, but examples are not the same as
the justice itself. Plato wondered how we are able to recognize justice when we
are unable to define it. He concluded
that an unambiguous Justice must exist in the metaphysical (non-material idea)
sense, and that we must once have known justice as an unchanging “Form” or we
would not be able to recognize examples of it.
Plato’s theory of Forms is based upon his belief that we are
born into the material world from an ideal immaterial world where our souls were acquainted with Justice, Goodness, Beauty and Love. We are able to recognize justice, goodness,
beauty and love because our souls have innate knowledge of these non-material
entities. This being so, none is justified in claiming that they do not know or cannot recognize justice, goodness, beauty and love. For Plato the good
life requires philosophical reflection on these Forms and taking responsibility for fulfilling one’s proper role in accordance with one's potential and nature. He supported censorship in society because he
believed that the citizen’s preoccupation with the trivial and mundane posed
obstacles to philosophical contemplation of the Forms. In other words, Plato believed that
there are pursuits and behaviors that can cause us to miss the good life. One such action was gossip or being a busybody. Plato wrote, “To do one’s own business and not to be a busybody is justice.” (Republic 433b.)
Aristotle rejected Plato’s definition of the good life as
contemplation of the eternal Forms. He
was not convinced that Forms have a real existence. Instead he argued that what
is to be known can be discovered from the study of nature. Our powers of
observation and critical reasoning can bring us reliable knowledge upon which
to base ethical decisions.
Aristotle did agree with Plato’s definition of virtue as
knowledge, but the knowledge that mattered to Aristotle was not the knowledge
of Forms, but self-knowledge of what brings one happiness or what causes one to
thrive. This is the basis for
eudaimonism, an ethical approach that holds personal happiness as the highest
good. This view will find different expressions in the centuries that follow,
most especially in the hedonism of Renaissance humanism.
This helped me with my moral and ethics of ancient Greece essay
ReplyDelete